subscribe to our mailing list:
|
SECTIONS
|
|
|
|
Prohibition to Think
By Mark Perakh
Posted on March 23, 2000
Contents
Breaking through an open door
Irrationality of opposite views
Are morals prescribed by God?
Pseudo-scientific proofs of God's extistence
Biology or teleology?
The Chosen People are the proof, or are they?
God's justice according to Kelemen
Kelemen's triumphant conclusion
Two arguments or four approaches?
Kelemen's "Deductive Argument"
The incunabular argument by Kelemen
Kelemen discusses scientific evidence
In this article I will discuss two books by Lawrence Kelemen, one titled Permission
to Believe (Targum Press, 1990) with a subtitle "Four Rational Approaches
to God's Existence" and the other titled Permission
to Receive (Targum Press, 1996) with a subtitle "Four Rational Approaches
to the Torah's Divine Origin."
At the very beginning of his first book Kelemen says (page 12): "First,
many people would believe in God tomorrow if only their intellect would allow
them. These people intuitively
suspect the existence of an Almighty. Yet
the admirably high value our society places on reason, combined with the
unfortunately widespread misconception that belief in God is necessarily
irrational, squelches their potential spirituality. These individuals should be permitted to examine the case for God. They
should be granted permission to believe."
Reading
the above sentences leaves one wondering whether Kelemen expects that his
potential readers will swallow any statement regardless of its meaning provided
it is delivered with sufficient solemnity, or he himself is a prisoner of
delusion.
Consider
the alleged prohibition to believe. Is
there an invisible "intellectual" police watching the beliefs of every
individual and forbidding him to believe? How
can Kelemen assert that "many people" (who are not believers) "intuitively
suspect" that there is God? Did
he conduct a survey of unbelievers who admitted that they "intuitively
suspect" the existence of "an Almighty"? (Note that in his assertion
Kelemen mentions not just God, but "an Almighty," hence attributing to the
object of the alleged suspicions of many non-believers a certain characteristic
– omnipotence).
In
Kelemen's view, adherence to reason "squelches one's potential
spirituality." Reason itself, in
Kelemen's view, is alien to spirituality.
Furthermore,
according to Kelemen, the view which asserts that belief in God is irrational,
is unfortunate. Note that in this
point Kelemen does not seem to be concerned with the question about whether
or not the belief in God is indeed rational. He is simply unhappy that many
people view such a belief as irrational, regardless of any arguments that might
confirm such a view. (We will discuss this question a little later in this
review).
Overall,
the above quotation defines the parameters of the discussion as being set on a
false foundation.
There
is no such problem as an absence of permission to believe either in the
existence of an Almighty God or in the divine origin of the Torah. Indeed, there are in our world many more believers than agnostics and
especially than atheists. The
latter are a rather rare breed but Kelemen's effort is aimed precisely at that
minority. To give more weight to his discourse, Kelemen depicts
agnostic and atheistic views as allegedly being prevalent (at least among
intellectuals) and owing their existence to a mythical prohibition to believe.
There
is a Russian adage "Breaking through an open door." If a door is open, there is no need to break through it. The
quoted adage relates to a situation in which an action is undertaken to achieve
a result that actually requires no effort because it is already available. Kelemen's effort to ensure "permission to believe" is breaking
through a door which is anyway already wide open for anyone wishing to believe.
Denying
the spirituality of non-believers, and falsely assuming that many non-believers
are somehow prohibited to believe, Kelemen actually is arguing not for permission to believe, as he pretends, but rather for a prohibition
against thinking.
In
this review, I will expand on the latter statement by discussing the particular
arguments forwarded by Kelemen to support his appeal to believe.
Chapter 1 in the first of the two Kelemen's books is titled "Atheism
is Irrational." To either agree or disagree with that statement, we need
first to agree on a definition of what is rational and what is irrational. Unfortunately, Kelemen does not offer any such definition. The absence of a definition of a concept utilized by Kelemen makes his
discourse rather vague. In order to
rationally discuss Kelemen's books, we have to introduce the
definition in question ourselves, since without it we will lack criteria
enabling us to distinguish between rational and irrational attitudes. Of course, introducing such a definition, we will have to make sure it
will not contradict the concept of rational vs irrational which seems to be
implicitly (possibly not always consistently) used by Kelemen.
For the purpose of this discussion, we will formulate the following
definition of a rational attitude to controversial issues. In order to be viewed as rational, the attitude must meet the following
requirements: 1) It must clearly distinguish between facts and the
interpretation of facts. 2) It must clearly distinguish between a) undeniable
facts proven by uncontroversial direct evidence, b) plausible but unproven
notions, c) notions agreed upon for the sake of discussion, d) notions that are
possible but not supported by evidence, and e) notions contradicting evidence. Also, when saying that the above situations must be clearly
distinguished in a rational discourse, they must be also accordingly judged in
regard to their veracity, so a rational conclusion is such that is based solely
on undeniable facts proven by uncontroversial direct evidence. Statements and
notions arrived at without meeting the above criteria we will view as
irrational, regardless of how many adherents they may have. A conclusion or view can be accepted as rational only if it is based on a
careful analysis of the matter with regards to its meeting the above points. Note that our definition does not contain any criteria designed to assert
that a notion, conclusion, or view in question is true. In other words, our definition of rational not necessarily
coincides with a definition of what is true, although in many cases (but not
necessarily always) that which is rational has a good chance of being true as
well.
With the above definition in mind, we can now discuss Kelemen's
assertion that of three possible
views, that held by believer in God, that held by an atheist, and that held by
an agnostic, only two (the believer's and the agnostic's) are rational while
that of an atheist is irrational.
In view of our definition, we must agree with Kelemen's
statement that atheism is irrational. It
is irrational, as per our definition (but not necessarily untrue) because there
is no direct incontrovertible evidence that there is no God. Note, that the last statement actually requires we first define the
notion of God. Since this paper is not a theological tractate, I am not trying
to provide such a definition. For
the purpose of this discussion, it seems sufficient to state that Kelemen's
God is the God of the Torah.
We can also agree with Kelemen that the views of agnostics are
rational. Agnostics do not adhere to any notions that are not supported by
direct uncontroversial evidence, so agnostics' views do not contradict our
definition of rationality.
It is the third part of Kelemen's triad of statements which is
contrary to our definition of rational vs. irrational. According to that view, religious beliefs are rational. It is easy to see that such a statement clearly contradicts the above
definition of rational.
There is no direct incontrovertible evidence of God's existence. What believers do offer as evidence is not facts but the interpretations
of facts. These interpretations may
be true or false, or partially true and partially false, but interpretations are
not facts and therefore religious beliefs, like atheism, are irrational,
according to our definition. If,
though, Kelemen is dissatisfied with our definition of rationality, he should
offer his own definition, but that would, of course, completely alter the
parameters of discussion.
To substantiate his assertion that religious beliefs can be
rational, Kelemen describes two possible ways the religious belief can be
acquired rationally.
One way, according to Kelemen, is that God may just "introduce
Himself to you" (page 15). He
continues: "Although we have a right to view such claim with extreme
skepticism, we must also admit that someone could come to possess absolute
certainty about God's existence through such an event."
That assertion is by no means compelling. If we accepted the quoted statement, we would have to legitimize
hallucinations which may result, say, from drug abuse or from a mental illness
if such a hallucination features God introducing himself to a person. If a person believes he is Napoleon or Jesus, we justifiably view this as
fully irrational and keep that person in a mental ward. If, though, a person
believes God introduced himself to him/her, then, according to Kelemen, this may
be viewed as a rationally substantiated belief. While some people may firmly
believe God spoke to them, we hardly can refute such a claim, but this belief is
no more rational than the belief of
being Napoleon or Jesus, or Mother Teresa, or one's own mother.
The second way to acquire faith rationally, says Kelemen (page 16)
is "through indirect evidence, that is, through circumstances and phenomena
that cannot be explained without positing God's existence."
Obviously, in the latter statement Kelemen sees no distinction between
facts and the interpretation of facts, and therefore, according to our
definition of the rational attitude, the second way, suggested by Kelemen for
acquiring faith, does not meet our definition of rational.
How can it be asserted that there is no way to explain a phenomenon other
than to posit the existence of God? If
such an alternative explanation is not evident it does not mean it is
impossible. Therefore, accepting the existence of God as the only possible
explanation of a phenomenon is by no means a rational act, as it is not based on
direct incontrovertible evidence and hence contradicts our definition of
rational. Both of Kelemen's ways
to acquire faith through a rational path turn out to be irrational emergences of
belief substantiated not by factual evidence but only by a certain
interpretation of facts.
To support his assertion that firm knowledge can be rational even
in the absence of direct evidence, Kelemen gives an example: "How do we know that there was once an American president by the name
of Abraham Lincoln? We know not because we ever met Lincoln but because there is
no other reasonable way to explain the existence of a universally accepted
tradition that he lived."
The fallacy of this pseudo-analogy is obvious. Kelemen's example would be more plausible if, instead of Lincoln, he
mentioned some person whose existence is indeed not fully certain, for example
some ancient king whose name is known from legends but whose historical
existence cannot be asserted as undeniable fact. Some biblical personalities come to mind, but I don't want to be
accused of being unfairly critical of the biblical account. Therefore I would suggest some semi-historical personality like some
Egyptian pharaoh whose name allegedly appears in some inscriptions. Since there cannot be absolute certainty that the inscriptions in
question have indeed been interpreted correctly, or that if they were, they
indeed reflect reality rather than fantasy of those who made them, the consensus
that this or that ancient pharaoh did live is built upon an argument similar to
that offered by Kelemen. It seems
most reasonable to interpret the inscriptions in question in a certain way and
therefore there is a consensus that the person in question did indeed live so
many thousand years ago. This
consensus is though not as compelling as direct evidence, such as obviously
exists about Lincoln. We possess
numerous documents, testimonies, and generally an enormous wealth of evidence
about Lincoln's life, activities and death. To know that Lincoln lived, it is not necessary to have personally met
him. There is not even a shadow of such direct evidence about the existence of
God. Rather then factual evidence,
the alleged evidence of God's existence is
just interpretation of facts. None
of those interpretations is compelling enough to exclude alternative
explanations and therefore to accept the interpretation attributing certain
facts to God's existence is purely irrational (which by itself does not
signify that the ensuing belief is wrong).
Furthermore, it is easy to give examples contrary to that with
Lincoln. There are quite often
situations when there is compelling evidence of some events but nevertheless
there are people who doubt or even deny the occurrence of those events
regardless of the evidence. One well-known example is the Holocaust. There is
overwhelming and undeniable evidence that the Nazis systematically murdered
millions of Jews and Gypsies. Nevertheless, there are, so far not very numerous but rather
noisy groups of people who fanatically deny those undeniable facts. Why is then this unusual or surprising that many people doubt the
existence of God, for which there is no clear and unambiguous evidence but only
particular interpretations of facts, which never exclude alternative
explanations?
As the matter stands now, Kelemen's opinion that only atheism is
irrational while agnosticism and religious belief are rational, seems
unsubstantiated. A more reasonable
notion seems to be that both atheism and religious beliefs are irrational, while
only agnosticism is rational. Again, rationality or irrationality in themselves do not
determine what is true and what is false, as either beliefs in God or atheism
must be true despite being irrational.
The
last portion of Chapter 1 in Kelemen's book is devoted to a discussion of the
allegedly strongest argument atheists can suggest against the existence of God. According to Kelemen, this argument boils down to the question: why do
bad things happen to good people?
Of
course, this question is by far not the first that comes to mind when discussing
the existence of God. This question
would be legitimate if the discussion were not about the existence of God, but
rather about the existence of a specific God who possesses particular
characteristics. Namely, it would
deal only with a God who is supposed to be, first, interested in humans, and,
second, benevolent. The question of
God's existence is, though, quite apart from the question of what kind of God
he is.
If
we assume that God exists, it still leaves open a number of alternatives as to
what kind of God he is. God may
have created the world and then left it alone, to proceed according to the laws
he established. God may also be
watching the world and sometimes interfering with its functioning, but remaining
utterly indifferent to humans. God
may have created humans just for fun, to see how they would behave and what they
would do. God may relate to humans
in the way similar to how we relate to animals. God may even be enjoying some cruel games with humans. All these
possibilities are not substantiated by any rational evidence, but they cannot be
excluded, as cannot be excluded the existence of an invisible God itself. An observation of the history of humankind
makes the assumption that God loves people least plausible, even though that is
what Kelemen's question seems to imply.
For
an agnostic or an atheist, the questionable assertion is, first and foremost,
whether or not an invisible God who has created the universe exists, or the
universe's existence is
spontaneous. The question of
God's benevolence seems to be somewhere lower on their list of priorities.
Kelemen
formulates his assertions in regard to which parts of his triad are rational and
which are irrational, in a rather categorical way, without trying to
substantiate them. It leaves an impression that he expects the readers to accept
these assertions uncritically. If that is true, it means he does not want to
permit the readers to think
Chapter
2 in Kelemen's first book is titled "The Moral Approach to God's
Existence." In that chapter Kelemen asks the following question: "Why is
murder wrong?" Testing a number
of possible answers to that question, Kelemen finds all of those answers
unsatisfactory and concludes that the only possible answer is that murder is
indeed wrong because God said so. The alternative explanations include reason, a
decision by some extremely influential human law-giver, the decision made by the
majority of people in our country, common opinion of the majority of all people,
and, finally, murder being unnatural.
Reason,
according to Kelemen cannot explain the notion that murder is wrong because
murder can easily be rationalized as being useful for achieving certain goals.
Decision
by some influential person cannot explain the notion in question because no
individual is powerful enough to impose his/her view on the society as a whole,
and, moreover, even the most influential person lives only for so many years so
his/her decision cannot serve as a permanent principle agreed upon by the
society.
The
decision by our society as a whole cannot explain the notion in question because
it will not have any effect on many other societies, including those that will
eventually replace our society.
Decision
by the entire community of nations cannot explain the notion that murder is
wrong because the community of nations is always in the process of change and
whatever seemed right at a particular moment of time, may be viewed as wrong
just for the next generation.
The
notion of murder being unnatural cannot explain why it is wrong because for many
individuals, groups and whole countries some forms of murder may seem quite
natural.
Hence,
concludes Kelemen, the only remaining option is to view the notion that murder
is wrong as having supernatural origin.
The
described puerile quasi-philosophical discourse by Kelemen makes one wonder,
what kind of readers he had in mind? The
above discourse may impress first-graders but otherwise it is a glaringly
primitive and factually unsubstantiated discussion.
What
does Kelemen mean by his question? Facts
are abundant showing that murder is too often viewed as not wrong at all. Most of the US states execute men and women for various crimes, and the
overwhelmingly religious people of the country equally overwhelmingly ardently
support death penalty. When Russian
troops prepare to fight the Chechen guerillas, Russian Orthodox priests perform
solemn prayers asking God to help in murdering Chechens. In their turn, when
Chechen guerillas and accompanying them international mercenaries and fanatical
Muslim volunteers embark on murderous raids into towns and villages, they ask
Allah for help in murdering Russians and those Chechens who do not want to die
fighting Russians. Therefore the very question – why is murder wrong – is
formulated in a wrong way. The
Tutsi and Hutu murdering each other, or Muslim rebels in Phillipines, or Marxist
gangs in Latin America obviously do not think at all that murder of those who do
not share their views is wrong.
The proper
question should be different and twofold. First,
why ten commandments include prohibition to murder and, second, why murder is a
crime under the laws of most of the countries unless it is performed with a
legal approval. The answer to that
question does not require any reference to supernatural source of morals. Unregulated murder is prohibited by law for the same reason a legally
regulated murder is permitted, namely because it is viewed as advantageous for
the majority of the population. It
is well known what happens when law and order break down in a country. Nobody is safe and the life becomes extremely hard. Prohibiting arbitrary murder and approving legally authorized murder both
are meant to make life more comfortable for the overwhelming majority of the
population.
There is
no need whatsoever to look for a supernatural source of the notion that the
murder is wrong, because, first of all, there is practically no such absolute
notion in existence. The inclusion of prohibition to kill into ten commandments
may be explained by the same reason murder is considered a punishable crime in
most of the law systems. If arbitrary murder were allowed, it would make life
hell-like in any society. Society
protects itself by proclaiming murder a crime and instituting punishment for it,
often in the form of murder. Ten
commandments can be viewed as a human-generated precursor of legal systems whose
main purpose was to reasonably regulate the society to the advantage of the
majority.
The second
book by Kelemen is aimed at proving the divine origin of the Torah. Therefore it is natural to expect that asserting the divine origin of the
moral imperatives, Kelemen would support his thesis by referring to the
pertinent elements of the Torah. Strangely, discussing the morals and
attributing the high moral principles to a supernatural source, Kelemen
completely avoids any discussion of the moral lessons one can receive from the
Torah. May it be that the reason
for such an omission is his reluctance to delve into the stories telling about
not very commendable behavior of many biblical personalities? One of the beloved heroes of the Bible, whose ancestry was supposed to
produce the future Messiah, king David treacherously took by force the wife of
his faithful servant and soldier Uriah and arranged for Uriah's murder. One of
David's sons raped his half-sister, thus aggravating rape by incest.
Discussing such examples, which are abundant in the biblical story, Kelemen
would encounter an unrewarding task of explaining how to reconcile all those
occurrences of crime, betrayal, incest and cowardice with the high moral
principles allegedly stemming from a divine source of the Torah. Having eschewed
such a discussion, Kelemen demonstrated a rather imperfect devotion to the
unadulterated truth.
The
entire chapter 2 in Kelemen's first book is void of any real analysis of
morals and of their origin but boils down to an irrelevant discourse not based
on any factual foundation. If
Kelemen expected the readers to accept his discourse uncritically, it means he did
not want the readers to think.
Chapter
3 in Kelemen's first book is titled "The Cosmological Approach to God's
Existence." Unlike the preceding
chapters, where Kelemen mainly dealt with generalities, in this chapter he
embarks on a journey through scientific data and theories, attempting to enlist
those data as evidence indicating the hand of God. There is nothing original or new in that chapter where
Kelemen repeats the same arguments heard hundreds of time before from the
proponents of the Bible's inerrancy, both of Jewish and Christian persuasions.
All those references to science have been shown many times over to be either
irrelevant or misinterpreted, but apparently no number of rebuttals, however
well founded, can persuade the adherents of the Bible's inerrancy to listen to
reason.
Of
course, there is nothing surprising in such an attitude. In my local newspaper there is a regular section titled "Faith and
Values." It prints numerous
letters from readers, some of them in favor of faith (overwhelmingly in its
Christian variety) and some in favor of science. More then once, in letters from believers an unequivocal opinion was
expressed that if there is a contradiction between science and the Bible, then
science surely is in error.
In
view of the above, I have no intention to discuss in detail the alleged
scientific proofs of God's existence borrowed by Kelemen from the books by his
fellow defenders of the biblical story. I
will make only a few brief comments.
In
the chapter in question, Kelemen tells the story of how science came to the
theory of the Big Bang. His narrative is more or less correctly following the
chain of events that culminated in the above theory, with only some minor
inaccuracies. He provides the same endlessly repeated quotes from scientists
allegedly supporting the biblical story about the creation of the universe. Of course, the factual side of the theory of the Big Bang in itself has
nothing to do with the question of whether the universe was created by God or
emerged spontaneously. The theory
of Big Bang, which is today the most widely accepted theory of the universe's
origin, cannot and does not answer that question. Equating the Big Bang theory
with the creation of the universe by God according to the biblical story is just
an interpretation of the theory in question in a way fitting the agenda of the
creationists. The theory itself
provides no clues whatsoever to the mystery of the universe's emergence. It is
worth mentioning that when a scientific theory seems to contradict the biblical
account, one of the arguments often used by the adherents of the Bible's
inerrancy is that "it is just a theory." For example, this argument is common in discussions of Darwin's theory
of evolution. Of course, Darwin's
theory is just a theory, and it does not pretend to be anything more than that. This is true, though, for every scientific theory, including that of the
Big Bang, but in the latter case the defenders of the Bible's inerrancy
readily forgive its being just a theory and refer to it as to a highly reliable
proof of their beliefs.
Generally
speaking, there are multiple points in the Bible which obviously contradict
scientific data. Some other points
seem to jibe well with such data. The
defenders of the Bible's inerrancy treat these two types of items differently. Those few points in the biblical story which seem to be in agreement with
science are touted as rational proofs of the veracity of the Bible. The Big Bang
theory is an example in point. However,
those, much more common points, which obviously are contrary to scientific data,
are either not mentioned, or subjected to a mental acrobatics to explain them
away. Examples are well known and
include such stories as the six days of creation, Noah and his ark, the order of
creation of plants, animals, and man, and many others.
If Kelemen expects readers to accept uncritically his contention that the
modern cosmology proves the existence of God, it means he wants to prohibit his
readers to think.
Chapter
4 in Kelemen's first book is titled "The Teleological Approach to God's
Existence." This title is somehow
misleading since actually it simply continues the theme of the preceding chapter
trying to prove God's existence by utilizing results of scientific
exploration. Like in the preceding
chapter, Kelemen again provides no new or original arguments repeating instead
the arguments heard countless number of times before from the defenders of the
Bible's inerrancy. This time
argumentation relates to biological sciences and to calculations of
probabilities. Kelemen repeats the references to the amazing complexity of the
universe and of the living organisms, which allegedly must have been a creation
of a divine Creator. He refers to
the very small probabilities of a spontaneous emergence of complex biological
structures ignoring the arguments showing that those small probabilities are
irrelevant. Without naming them, he
uses the so-called strong anthropic
principle and argument from design,
both discussed many times before. Both arguments have failed to make any skeptic
change his/her opinion and to both arguments many strong counter-arguments had
been suggested before. In this web site, both types of arguments together with
rebuttals have been discussed in several articles and therefore I see no reason
to repeat that discussion once again.
If
Kelemen expects the readers to accept his assertions uncritically, it means he
wants to impose on the readers a prohibition to think.
Chapter
5 in Kelemen's first book is titled "The Jewish History Approach to God's
Existence."
Kelemen
started with repeating in a condensed form the biblical story about the Jews who
were slaves in Egypt and then, some 3,300 years ago, miraculously escaped from
bondage while all other ethnic groups enslaved in Egypt perished. Then he continues to tell us that the escaped Jews arrived, less than
half a century later, at the border of what would become their God-promised
land.
Apparently
feeling that repeating the biblical story and providing no additional evidence
would not make his position convincing enough, Kelemen tries to provide some
independent evidence. Unfortunately,
his references are either misleading or unreliable.The indisputable fact is that there is no archeological or
documentary evidence that would support the biblical story.Extensive archeological exploration of the Sinai peninsula and in Israel
have so far failed to unearth any evidence in question.
For example, the
exodus of the Jews from Egypt, according to the Torah, is assumed to have
happened some 3,300 years ago. There is a plethora of material evidence from
that time related to the history of Egypt. There is not a word there about the Jewish slaves, about the ten plagues
of the biblical story, about the exodus of close to 2.5 million slaves, etc. It
is worth mentioning that among Egyptian documents of that epoch there is one
containing a detailed account about the escape of two slaves from their master,
with a description of the path they chose and of their capture. On the other hand, can we believe that the exodus of 2.5 million Jews did
not merit a single word in any of the documents of that time?
Regarding
the number of Jews who allegedly escaped from slavery, the book of Exodus
informs us that there were about 600,000 men in their ranks. Since there must have been an almost equal number of women,
and there were also children, there is a tradition estimating the total number
of Jews Moses led out of Egypt as close to 2.5 million. Since there were many
other ethnic groups living on the Earth at that time, the total population of
the planet must have comprised many millions. Indeed, in Deuteronomy 7.7 we
read: "for you are the fewest of all people."
We will
now discuss the population numbers in terms of orders of magnitude only, since
no precise numbers are known. Assume that the entire population of the earth at
the time of the Exodus was about ten million, which seems to be a rather
conservative estimate if we accept, as per the Torah, that there were about 2.5 million of Jews alone. Assume further that the duration of each generation was about fifty
years, which of course is probably an exaggerated number (even in the 17th
century the average life-span of men and women, especially of low social status,
was still less than 40 years only). In
other words, to avoid acceptance of numbers too favorable for my thesis, we will
use the term generation assuming that
every fifty years a new generation of people, larger than that of their parents,
completely replaced the preceding generation. Of course, such an assumption is somehow arbitrary, but remember that we
are estimating population growth in terms of orders of magnitude only. If we accept the above numbers, it means that between the Flood and the
Exodus, that is during about 1,000 years, twenty generations consecutively
replaced each other. According to
the Torah's story, only eight people (Noah, his wife, his three sons and their
wives) survived the Flood, but one thousand years after the Flood there were
already about 2.5 millions of Jews alone which makes our estimate of the entire
population of the earth at the time of Exodus as ten million quite conservative.
With these assumptions, the rate of the population's growth between the Flood
and the Exodus can be found to be 2.02 per generation. (For those interested in the arithmetic, the formula for the growth rate r is: r equals root of power n
of [M divided by m], where r is the growth
rate, M is the population size at the
end of the period in question, m is
the population size at the beginning of that period, and n is the number of generations. With the above assumptions, it
yields the rate of about 2.02 per generation). In other words, the assumptions based on the data given in the Torah lead
to the conclusion that the population of the earth more than doubled every fifty
years between the Flood and the Exodus. Since
our estimate of the entire population of the earth at the time of the Exodus (10
million) was deliberately chosen low, the rate of the population growth
necessary to fit the Torah's story must have actually been substantially
larger than 2.02 p/g.
Let
us see now what happens if we apply the above rate of population growth to the
period between the Exodus and our time, i.e. during 3,300 years. If the time span per generation is still estimated as 50 years, 66
generations must have replaced each other, and the earth population must have
more than doubled every fifty years. If
there were about 2.5 million Jews in Egypt at the time of the Exodus, than the
entire population of that country must have included at least as many people. Indeed, according to the archeological data, the population of Egypt
about 3,300 years ago was close to 2.5 million people. Assuming the rate of the population's growth to be the same 2.02 p/g
also for the period of time after the Exodus, we find that the population of
Egypt should have now reached (2.5 million times 2.02 to the power of 66) which
yields an absurdly enormous number of about (3.5 times ten to the power of 27). Of course the actual size of the population of the entire Earth today is
still immensely smaller, only about (5 times ten to the power of 9).
The
absurdity of the above data shows that something is wrong with the biblical
account.
Of
course, one can play with numbers, varying the assumptions about the duration of
a generation, or about the population size at the time of the Exodus, but there
is no way to make these numbers
reasonably compatible with the biblical story. For example, decreasing the estimate of the population size at the time
of the Exodus to below 10 million would increase the calculated rate of growth
for the period of time between the Exodus and our time, however one cannot
reasonably assume much less than 10 million remaining anywhere close to the biblical account of about 2.5 million of
Jews alone. Increasing the duration of a lifetime of a generation would also
increase the calculated rate of growth per generation, but the larger rate of
growth would be counterbalanced by the decreased number of generations between
the Flood and the Exodus. Furthermore, each variation of the assumed numbers
which would make the numbers for the millennium between the Flood and the Exodus
slightly more reasonable, would necessarily make the numbers for the millennia
between the Exodus and our time even farther from anything reasonable.
Another
counter-argument can be offered as follows. Average numbers are often misleading. The discrepancy between the data calculated for the first millennium
after the Flood and those for the following 3,300 years could be attributed to
the variations in the growth rate in the course of the millennia.
Generally
speaking, this is a valid argument. However,
it is hardly applicable to the case under consideration, for two reasons. First,
while average values are indeed sometimes misleading, the longer the time span
over which the averaging is done, the better are the fluctuations of the growth
rates smoothened out, and therefore the comparison of average rates for two very
long periods of time (in our case millennia) becomes meaningful. Second, to explain away the discrepancy in question by assuming that it
is due to the averaging of rates of growth, we would need to assume that the
rate of population's growth during the first millennium after the Flood was
much larger than during the next three millennia. Such a suggestion not only lacks any evidence, but it is contrary to the
known facts. Over the course of millennia, the advances in medicine and food production resulted in a slow and uneven, but gradual
increase in the average duration of human life, hence to a gradual increase of
the excess of births over deaths, thereby increasing the average rate of
population's growth. It is actually only a very recent phenomenon that in some
European countries (Russia is one example) a considerable drop in the number of
births occurs, but even this is more than counterbalanced by an immense
population growth in some other countries (like Mexico, and others). To assume
that the rate of population growth during the first thousand years after the
Flood was much larger than it was for the next 3,300 years is hardly tenable.
These
simple calculations, however crude estimates they are, show that the three
biblical numbers – only eight survivors of the Flood, about one thousand years
between the Flood and the Exodus and about 2.5 million Jews at the time of
Exodus -- cannot all be correct.
The biblical assertions that there were only eight people alive after the Flood,
but about 2.5 million Jews alone one thousand years later, plus the fact that
about 5 billion people are living on the earth today cannot be reasonably
reconciled and therefore are untenable. Consequently (as well as because of many
other inconsistencies) the biblical account cannot be relied upon in discussing
the history of the Jews, at least until the time of the Kings. Even the early history of the Kings, including that of the allegedly
great states ruled by David and especially by Solomon, has no archeological
confirmation whatsoever.
Despite
many efforts, no archeological evidence of the Israelis in Sinai has been
unearthed. As the recent
archeological studies in Israel have shown, there are no archeological traces of
the conquest of Canaan by Jewish tribes under the guidance of Yehoshua (Joshua)
Bin Nun. There were almost no
cities in existence at the time of the supposed conquest like those mentioned in
the Torah. The few settlements that really existed were just small villages,
usually not protected by any fortifications. There are no traces of the battles that reportedly destroyed those
villages.
In
view of the above facts, the ancient history of the Jews as told by Kelemen is mostly just a legendary story
not supported by any documentary or archeological evidence. Kelemen's references to alleged archeological confirmations of the
biblical account contradict the results of the recent more thorough and more
comprehensive archeological studies. There is a widely accepted consensus among
Israeli archeologists that their earlier expectations and hopes of unearthing
evidence of the biblical narrative related to the Exodus or to the Israelite
conquest of Canaan have been thwarted by the practically complete absence of
such evidence, and, moreover, by unearthing evidence which is contrary to the
biblical story.
When
Kelemen switches to the more recent history of the Jewish people, he is
generally on much more solid ground (even though his narrative about the story
of Jews in historically known Hellenistic and Roman periods has a number of
imprecise elements). Overall, his brief description of the endless persecutions
the Jews experienced in the course of the last two millennia is unfortunately
true. Yes, the Jewish people were
subjected to various forms of oppression, murdered en masse, and expelled from various countries. Various forms of
anti-Semitism, that extremely stubborn moral plague of which humankind should be acutely ashamed (but seems not to be) persist to this
day. It is a complicated phenomenon
whose roots are varied. However unique the history of the Jewish people, it also
has features in common with many other ethnic and religious groups.
Ancient
Carthage was erased from the face of the earth by victorious Romans and its
population largely massacred. The
Mongol warriors of Genghis Khan murdered the entire population of the cities in
Central Asia they captured. Attila
the Hun was hardly much more lenient. While
all these events are of the remote past, in our time the monstrous regime of Red
Khmers murdered almost half of the country's population. Tutsi and Hutus engaged in mutual mass murder in full view of the world. Stalin expelled whole nations to remote corners of his realm. This gruesome list could be expanded. Hence, Jews have no monopoly on suffering and persecutions.
Various
theories have been offered to explain the roots of anti-Semitism, but none
seemed to be satisfactory. This
makes it easier for Kelemen to suggest that the history of the Jewish people has been preordained by a supernatural
power. While such a supposition
cannot be excluded, it has not been supported by any evidence and is no more
plausible than a variety of explanations attributing the vicissitudes of the Jews to natural causes. The
persecutions of Jews by the Romans can be plausibly explained by the
irreconcilable contradiction between the monotheism of Jews versus the Romans'
belief in a multitude of gods, including their very human emperors. The endless revolts by Jews who could not reconcile themselves to the
Roman pantheon and to the worship of every next emperor, provoked very harsh
reprisals. The persecutions of Jews
in the medieval times can be attributed to the traditional hostility of
Christian believers to the people who, as those benighted Christians believed,
betrayed and demanded killing their God's human body. Such explanations are by no means weaker than the attribution of the
Jewish fate to a divine power.
Kelemen
repeats the traditional interpretation of Jewish travails by attributing them to
the disobedience by Jews of God's commandments, as it was allegedly predicted
in the Torah. This question has been discussed, in particular in the paper on
this website titled "Dreaming Up..." It
was shown in that paper that the actual fate of the Jewish people has differed
in many respects from what could be expected based on Moses's prediction in
the book of Deuteronomy, and that those predictions by Moses are rather vague
and even contradictory. The
attribution of the events of the Jewish history to their disobedience to God's
commandments as the latter were listed in the Torah is not very convincing
because of the mentioned contradictions.
At
the end of this chapter Kelemen sais: "...one who feels dissatisfied with the
non-religious responses to the riddle of Jewish endurance can certainly find in
the history of this unusual people permission to believe."
That
quotation is strikingly illogical and built on sand. Nobody lacks "permission to believe," such
"permission" is available for free and without a ration card to everybody. Furthermore, why dissatisfaction with certain theories and explanations
must "certainly" be an argument in favor of some other, also unsatisfactory
theory or beliefs, is Kelemen's secret.
If
Kelemen expects his readers to accept his contentions uncritically it means he
wants to prohibit his readers' thinking.
Chapter
6 in Kelemen's first book is titled "Why Bad Things Happen to Good
People."
The
question in the chapter's title relates to a problem which is beyond
Kelemen's proclaimed topic of his book, namely to provide four rational
approaches to God's existence. The
question about God's justice or injustice is not about whether or not God
exists. This question implies not
only that the existence of God is accepted but also that we know God's
character. Certainly, accepting the hypothesis that the universe was created by
invisible immaterial God does not necessarily mean that the Creator also is
interested in humans, or cares about them, or is benevolent to them. Kelemen's question in the chapter's title implies, however, that God
is supposed to be benevolent to humans and therefore the bad things that
obviously happen to good people require an explanation.
Within
the framework of a rational discussion, this problem is irrelevant as long as
the very existence of a Creator has not been rationally substantiated. Since the preceding discourse by Kelemen failed to rationally
substantiate the existence of a Creator, the entire sixths chapter is
irrelevant.
Kelemen's
answer to the question in the title boils down to the following statement (page
94): "The fact that good people suffer and evil people prosper thus remains a
challenge only to one who would posit God's existence but reject the existence
of a soul and of afterlife."
Hence,
according to Kelemen, the confirmation of the hypothesis of God's existence is
provided by another hypothesis, that of the existence of a "soul" and an
afterlife.
A
hypothesis supported by another hypothesis, both lacking any factual evidence
but rather based only on a convoluted mental exercise, is what Kelemen tries to
sell as rational argument in favor of his beliefs.
If Kelemen
expects his readers to accept his allegedly rational arguments uncritically, he
actually tries to prohibit his readers' thinking.
In
the Epilogue to his first book Kelemen triumphantly concludes (page 98): "For
the staunch agnostic, prospects are dim. The only remaining option is to posit
God's existence. Worse yet, the theological solution seems to meet the
scientific criteria of a good theory. We can account for every aspect of reality
by making the one assumption that a moral Creator/Designer chose the Jews and
gave them the Torah."
Well,
congratulations to Mr. Kelemen who has so well convinced himself of his thesis. For the skeptical readers, though, the above quotation is preposterously
self-aggrandizing and unsubstantiated. In
his first book Kelemen failed to prove a single item on his agenda suggesting
instead a host of arbitrary, often factually wrong and always at least doubtful
contentions. Let us see if he did
better in his second, equally popular book.
Apparently
encouraged by the popularity of his first book, Kelemen tried to make his second
book to seemingly follow a similar format, again presenting four
approaches to determine the origin of the Torah. However, even a perfunctory
glance at Kelemen's second book immediately reveals that his four alleged ways
are present only in the book's title. Kelemen's
actual argumentation is only two-fold, while the book also contains some
additional chapters in which material not really germane to Kelemen's goal –
proving the divine origin of the Torah – is discussed.
Of
course the task Kelemen encountered in his second book was principally different
from that in his first book. In the
first book, Kelemen argued about a question to which there is no real answer. Kelemen probably realized that there are no unassailable rational
arguments either in favor of or against the belief in God, the Creator of the
universe. He correctly indicated that atheism is an irrational belief
that cannot be rationally proved or disproved. Of course, with his goal in mind, he refused to admit that faith is
equally irrational. I would like to emphasize again that "irrational" is by
no means equivalent to "wrong." Indeed,
either there is a God or there is no God. There
is no third alternative. If there is a God, then faith, although irrational, is
correct. If there is no God, then
atheism, although irrational, is correct. Obviously, in making the last two statements, I admit that,
as an agnostic, I adhere to a view which is neither true nor wrong, since there
are only two possible alternatives. However,
since the answer to the question of God's existence is unknown and cannot be
found rationally, I am right in the sense that I limit myself only to rational
arguments, and within the framework of a rational discussion agnosticism is, in my view, the only logically
justified position.
In
his first book Kelemen was relatively safe in regard to the main theme of his
discourse. While critics could pounce upon his particular arguments and show
their weakness or even evident errors (as I did in the preceding sections) they
could not provide any valid rational counter-arguments against his claim of
God's existence.
In
his second book Kelemen is on much weaker ground. Now he tries to prove that the Torah was indeed given by God
to the Jewish people. Hence, rather
than discussing the unanswerable question of God's existence, here Kelemen
had, first, to judge God's mind and, second, suggest rational arguments
proving his thesis. This is an
obvious case where the burden of proof is on Kelemen.
While
suggesting his alleged proofs of the Torah's divine origin, Kelemen avoids any
discussion of the multiple well-known discrepancies and controversies that
plague the text of the Torah. Does
Kelemen not know about those preposterous inconsistencies? It is hardly likely. Indeed,
in this book Kelemen devoted a good portion of his discourse to a question which
is actually extraneous to his topic, namely to discrepancies in the New
Testament. Kelemen discussed those contradictions rather aptly,
demonstrating that different books of the New Testament tell incompatible
stories. For example, the Gospel of
Matthew informs the readers that there were twenty-eight generations between
David and Jesus. The Gospel of Luke
counts instead forty-three generations. The
names of Jesus's ancestors are quite different in the lists provided by Mathew
and Luke. Moreover, if Jesus was
born due to a virginal conception, why was he considered a descendant of David
through Joseph who, according to the Gospels, was not really his father? Another inconsistency Kelemen indicated is the conflicting reports in
different Gospels about the appearance of Jesus to his disciples after his
resurrection. It is unclear from the Gospels where the resurrected Jesus appear,
in Jerusalem or in the Galilee, the two accounts irreconcilably contradicting
each other.
Having
thus demonstrated his attention to the inconsistency in the religious sources
related to a faith Kelemen does not share, he strangely lost all of his
inquisitiveness when discussing the Torah. In the very beginning of the book of Genesis, one encounters an
irreconcilable contradiction between Genesis 1 and Genesis 2 in their respective
stories about the order of creation. There are many other inconsistencies in the Torah. Since Kelemen's goal was to prove the divine origin of the Torah, he
would be expected to provide an explanation for the numerous discrepancies and
inconsistencies obvious to anybody reading the text of the Torah. Kelemen's failure to even mention those discrepancies seriously impairs
his argumentation.
Let
us see what arguments Kelemen does offer in support of his thesis.
In the chapter thus titled, Kelemen suggests some criteria for
distinguishing between revelations from God and man-originated ideas by
providing a definition of the features one could expect from a divine
revelation.
At the very beginning of that chapter, Kelemen explains that his
following argumentation presupposes the existence of God. His task now is to identify God's message, hence for those readers who
doubt the existence of God, the following discourse is moot.
Actually, besides accepting the existence of God, Kelemen makes
two more assumptions. One additional assumption is that God is not just the
Creator of the universe, but that he is also good. This assumption is suggested without any substantiation. If God indeed created the universe (which is possible) it does not mean
that God continues to interfere with nature he created, or that he is interested
in the fate of the humankind, or in the fate of each particular individual, or,
if he is interested, he is benevolent rather than cruel or just playing games
with humans for unknown purpose or simply for fun. Each of the listed alternatives may be possible even though none can be
substantiated by incontrovertible evidence. Finally, Kelemen suggests a third
assumption (which, in his view, is a consequence of the preceding two
assumptions) that God must have wished to communicate with humankind, to reveal
himself. Of course, there is no
proof for that assumption either.
Having adopted the above assumptions, Kelemen says (page 22):
"He (God) must make religion accessible for the sensible and sober-minded. He
must provide the components necessary to construct a logical bridge from generic
monotheism to a specific revelation." Kelemen
then attempts to identify such components and to assemble such a "bridge."
The way of reasoning suggested by Kelemen is as follows. There are thousands of religions in existence. However, Kelemen is interested only in reviewing monotheistic religions,
since non-monotheistic faiths cannot, by definition, carry a message from an
omnipotent God who is the only one Creator of the universe and of its laws. If God, as Kelemen asserted, must have revealed himself to humankind,
then at least one of the monotheistic religions must be the depository of
God's revelation. He reviews the principal tenets of a number of monotheistic
religions, including Judaism, Islam, Christianity, Sikhism, and the Bahai faith. Among these faiths, says Kelemen, Judaism has the oldest tradition and
was the first to introduce the idea of monotheism, explicitly expressed in the
Torah. The rest of the monotheistic
religions borrowed the main principle of an omnipotent God from Judaism, and all
those monotheistic religions accept the divine origin of the Torah. The difference between Judaism and the rest of the monotheistic religions
is in that Judaism preserves the principle that the Torah is the word of God
which cannot and will not ever be altered, while all the rest of the
monotheistic religions maintain that their founders received an updated message
from God superceding that of the Torah. So,
the Christian faith adheres to the idea that the Torah is the word of God
revealed through Moses, but maintains that the revelation was updated through
Jesus whose teachings are given in the Gospels thus superceding the Torah
wherever there is a difference between the Torah and the Gospels. One more tenet of Christianity is that there cannot and will not ever be
any alteration of Jesus's teachings, in every word and even a letter. Islam,
in its turn, acknowledges that the Torah is the word of God delivered through
Moses, as well as the New Testament is an update revealed through Jesus, but
maintains that those revelations were updated again through Mohammed and given
in the Koran, thus superceding both the Torah and the Gospels. Islam also maintains that Mohammed was the last prophet and
his teachings cannot and will not ever be changed. In its turn Sikhism, which originated in the 15th century,
accepts the Torah, the Gospels, and the Koran as the word of God, but maintains
that God had provided one more revelation through Nanak which supercedes the
earlier revelations of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam. Likewise, the Bahai faith, which originated in the 19th
century, accepts the divine origin of the Torah, the Gospels and the Koran, but
maintains that the teachings of the founders of that faith, most notably of Bab,
supercede the earlier revelations. Hence,
concludes Kelemen, there are irreconcilable contradictions between the above
monotheistic religions, except for one point they all accept. That point is the divine origin of the Torah. The listed monotheistic religions differ in their view on whether or not
the Torah's revelation was superceded by those delivered through later
prophets.
However, says Kelemen, if one accepts the divine origin of the Torah, one
has to accept an assertion repeated twenty-three times in the Torah which states
that the Torah is the depository of
the ultimate truth providing the eternal law for all generations. Therefore, concludes Kelemen, the Torah is the best choice to be viewed
as the genuine word of God.
Then Kelemen discusses possible arguments against his conclusion. One possible counter-argument envisioned by Kelemen is the suggestion
that maybe assertions of the Torah's eternal and unalterable truthfulness were
inserted by Moses while God actually meant that it would be replaced by the
Gospels, the Koran, etc. Kelemen dismissed this argument by referring to God's
omnipotence. If God chose Moses as
the conduit for revelations, he certainly knew that Moses would faithfully
convey the message.
Another possible counter-argument envisioned by Kelemen is that
the very appearance of later supposed revelations which started new mass
religions is proof of God's defeat. Here Kelemen makes an unexpected
statement. He says, "We must remember, however, that most people do not select
their religion solely for intellectual reason. Of course, religion must make sense, too; but most people affiliate
primarily because they were born into that religion, because it validated their
(not necessarily intellectually rooted) feelings and/or values, or because they
enjoy that religion's holidays and rituals."
Excellent. Suddenly there
is, among the nebulous verbiage, a simple and reasonable statement of an
indisputable fact. One is entitled to ask: "What were the reasons you, Kelemen,
affiliated with Judaism? Were you
not born into that religion? Don't you find that it validates your (not
necessarily intellectually rooted) feelings and/or values? Don't you enjoy the Jewish holidays and rituals?" If the listed
reasons are sufficient for affiliation with a religion, then all the attempts to
rationalize faith are superfluous.
Accepting that statement, we can reasonably view all the preceding
discussion of monotheistic
religions as based on sand. The
fact that Christians, Moslems, Sikhs, and Bahais agree with the Jews that the
Torah was a revelation from God, cannot mask the fact that all these religions
explicitly deny that the Torah was the ultimate word of God and insist that
their sacred books superceded the Torah. Kelemen
himself supplies quotations to that effect (page 33). He writes: "...each
subsequent religion absolutely denies the current validity of its predecessor(s)." The sacred texts of Christians, Moslems, Sikhs and Bahais unequivocally
maintain that they replaced the Torah and even threaten those who still view the
Torah as the depository of ultimate truth with disasters and punishments. Hence,
the assertion that the monotheistic religions that came after Judaism all agree
on the question of the Torah's veracity is simply contrary to facts. In various ways, all these religions reject the Jewish belief that the
ultimate truth is deposited in the Torah. Since
Kelemen himself quotes the pertinent verses from the sacred books of
Christianity, Islam, and Sikhism, he obviously, not noticing his inconsistency,
defeats his own most crucial thesis which in his view proves that the Torah is
indeed a direct message from God.
What if, however, Kelemen's assertions were true, and Muslims,
Sikhs, Bahais and Christians indeed fully share with Jews an acceptance of the
Torah as the only genuine word of God? What would it prove? It would prove only
just that - that many millions of people have certain beliefs. This by no means
would signify that the Torah is indeed the direct word of God. Many millions of men and women hold beliefs which Kelemen certainly views
as nothing more than superstitions. Millions
of men and women firmly believe that a son of a carpenter from a small town in
the Galilee created the universe, but Kelemen surely does not share that belief. Millions of men and women firmly believe that a merchant from the city of
Mecca ascended to heaven and talked there with God, but Kelemen hardly shares
that belief either. Hence, even if Muslims, Christians, Sikhs and Bahais indeed
shared Kelemen's belief that only the Torah is the direct word of God, such a
belief would not prove that the Torah is indeed that. Since, though, the adherents of the listed religions actually do not
share Kelemen's assertion, his alleged proof has no evidentiary value
whatsoever and proves nothing.
As mentioned earlier, discussing the question of whether the Torah
is indeed the only one genuine revelation of God, Kelemen pretends not to know
about the glaring inconsistencies and contradictions obvious to readers of the
Torah. Explaining those inconsistencies would be surely more
appropriate when trying to prove the divine origin of the Torah. Since Kelemen avoided any attempts to discuss the
inconsistencies in question, his whole discussion
looks irrelevant. If Kelemen
expected his readers to accept his contentions uncritically, he prohibited his
readers' thinking.
To additionally support his thesis about the divine origin of the
Torah, Kelemen suggests what he calls an "external check." The idea of that particular discourse is to figure out what a "good"
God would give his beloved people. In
Kelemen's terms, it is "job"
rather than "charity." Indeed,
in a human society, says Kelemn, to get a job is certainly preferable to
receiving charity.
Elaborating,
Kelemen writes (page 35): "Since we are all God's children, it follows that
one of God's highest priorities would be kindness and general improvement of
the human conditions. His assignment would therefore include performing and
encouraging kindness, acting righteously, spreading happiness and peace, and
heightening respect for human rights." Indeed? So far, God seems not to have been very successful in achieving the goals
listed by Kelemen. When
millions of Jews were led to the gas chambers of Aushwitz and Majdanek, they
experienced first-hand God's kindness, promotion of righteousness and a vast
improvement of the human condition, were they not.
Continuing
his pious abracadabra, Kelemen conducts his "external check" by reviewing
whether or not the Torah does indeed provide people with an "assignment"
that corresponds to what allegedly should be expected from a divine source. This "external check" consists of several components, namely ethics,
complexity, and individual creativity.
In the
section on ethics, Kelemen asserts that the ten commandments of the Torah are
the most principal foundations for ethics. If this were the extent of Kelemen's discussion of ethics, I would
readily agree since, indeed, most of the ten commandments of the Torah are very
important constituents of ethics. They have certainly played an enormous role in
establishing the humane and reasonable rules of conduct for a civilized society. The origin of those ten commandments is though a completely different
question. Continuing his discourse, Kelemen reaches beyond the ten commandments.
He maintains that the Torah also provides a detailed system of justice, based on
high moral principles. On page 37,
he lists the ethical guidelines given in the Torah, a total of 18 items,
including the prohibition against disobeying court decisions, animal abuse,
self-righteousness and many others. Moreover,
says Kelemen, the Torah not only prohibits unethical behavior, but forbids even
fantasizing about it. For example, "parallel to the positive order 'Love
your brother,' the Torah enjoins 'Do not hate your brother in your
heart.'" Well, I hope that after having read my comments, Kelemen,
fulfilling the Torah's enjoinment, will not hate me even in his heart, but
rather will love me as a brother.
As to the
moral imperatives dictated by the Torah, let us recall that the Torah describes,
usually without an explicit disapproval, such deeds of the chosen people as
conquering cities by means of treacherous subterfuges. (In example, when, in a
way of reprisal for a crime committed against them by the inhabitants of a town,
Israelites promised mercy if the people of that town convert to Judaism, having
no intention to keep their word. As
soon as the men of that town were subjected to circumcision, and were
temporarily incapacitated, the Israelites massacred them). Time and time again, the Torah tells us how Yehoshua "smote" this or
that group of people, these actions apparently in full agreement with the
commandment "Thou shalt not kill." The only
consolation I find in those stories is that the archeological data seem to
indicate that the Yehoshua's heroic deed most probably never happened, hence
the Israelites of that time did not conquer cities by treacherous tricks and did
not massacre the inhabitants of the promised land. I prefer to rather doubt the
divine origin of the Torah and the veracity of its stories than to believe that
my ancestors resorted to treachery and massacres thus negating the ethical
imperatives of the allegedly divinely-produced commandments.
In the next
two sections (pages 38 through 42) Kelemen's thesis is that the task assigned
the people by the Torah must be complex. Kelemen explains that point as follows (page 35): "God should provide
us with a highly detailed project so that we could also be rewarded for our task's complexity." This
definition reminds me of a man I met many years ago in a swimming pool. Having dropped into the water, he started very actively moving his hands
and legs. All his movements seemed to be exactly right as would be
expected from an accomplished swimmer. However,
despite all the energy he invested in his swimming effort, he remained
practically in the same spot, moving at best a few inches forward before getting
exhausted. Now, reading Kelemen's
discourse about the complexity of the task God should assign people, I have the
same impression – all the right moves being made, with no overall movement
resulting from it. Looking at
Kelemen's assertion that God is expected to have provided the people with a
complex task, I see that all the right words seem to be in place, but no meaning
seems to be behind those words. I
have taught quantum mechanics, statistical physics, quantum theory of solids,
theory of elasticity, thermodynamics etc., to both undergraduate and graduate
students. These subjects are
commonly acknowledged to be not among the very simple ones. I have had no
serious problems in understanding those disciplines and explaining them to my
students. Now, however, I stop in
puzzlement trying to figure out what is the deep meaning of Kelemen's thesis
of the complexity of the task assigned by God.
Kelemen
discusses three aspects of the complexity in question.
The first
aspect is what he calls "A Behavioral Index," (pages 39-40). Let us see if
we find in that section a clarification of the necessary complexity of a
God-assigned task. He writes (page 39): "First, a job is complex to the extent
that it involves many precise actions." I
don't believe this definition makes sense. If there is a job description in
which every step of the job is precisely prescribed, it can be performed by a
person with limited intelligence. The complexity of a job is determined by the
extent a person performing that job is required to make hard decisions in
unexpected and complex situations, which seems to be quite different from
Kelemen's definition. Based on
his definition, Kelemen refers to the very large number of detailed
prescriptions in the Torah in regard to many situations a person may encounter.
Indeed, there are in the Torah 613 categories of "mitzvoth." To elaborate
them, commentators had to compile the "Code of Jewish Laws" which contains
15,000 sections, covering many facets of human behavior. This fact, in Kelemen's view, points to the divine origin of the Torah
as it meets his requirements for the complexity of a God-assigned task.
Besides the
obscurity of Kelemen's assertion about the necessary complexity of a
God-assigned task, the factual side of Kelemen's elaboration is far from
convincing. The multitude of
regulations of human behavior prescribed by the Torah is by no means unique. Very detailed discussions of behavioral matters as well as of many other
subjects, comparable in size to that of the Code of Jewish Laws are not at all
uncommon, both in various religious and philosophical systems and in many other
areas of human endeavor. Many
computer programs contain hundreds of commands (sometimes more than 613) and
some manuals explaining these programs run to many hundreds of pages. Commonly used handbooks on physics and chemistry, or on various facets of
engineering contain sometimes thousands of entries. Consider just a good dictionary of a language, such as, for example the
complete Oxford Dictionary of English with its hundreds of thousands of entries. It prescribes how to interpret and use every word of the language. From
the standpoint of complexity these sources substantially exceed the
prescriptions and rules given in the Torah. Of course, nobody ever suggested that a good dictionary or handbook
is of divine origin. The criterion
of complexity (behavioral index) as rendered by Kelemen is irrelevant.
Two more
aspects of complexity suggested by Kelemen are what he calls "A Conceptual
Index," and "Individual Creativity." I will avoid discussing those two sections not because I see in them any
convincing arguments but simply to eschew falling into the pit of a very
prolonged discussion of a subject which, in Kelemen's rendition, does not seem
to deserve such a detailed analysis. Instead,
let us turn to the next chapter in Kelemen's second book, titled "The
Incunabular Argument."
The word incunabular
stems from a Latin root meaning "cradle." Books that appeared earlier than 1501 are referred to as incunabula.
Another, less specific meaning of that word is an ancient artifact. It
is unclear what does Kelemen mean by the title of that chapter. Actually, when we read the chapter in question, we do not find there any
argument that could be related to any "incunabular" topic. What we actually find in that chapter is a comparison of traditions that
are at the core of various religions and an assertion that the traditions of
Judaism is the only reliable and highly plausible ones.
Kelemen
first reviews a number of relatively "new" religions such as Mormonism,
Eckancar, the Unification church of Rev. Moon, Theosophy etc., all of them based
on a claim by only one, or as in Mormonism, according to Kelemen, by only two
persons who claimed to get a personal message directly from God and thus founded
a new religion. Kelemen's opinion
is that the claims of all those religions cannot be verified because in every
case the claims of the religion's founder(s) are not supported by
corroborative evidence from a substantial number of witnesses. Of course, that assertion is true. However,
each of those religions has a large number of followers who believe the claims
of the founders of this or that version of faith, and Kelemen does not even try
to discuss the reasons for the acceptance of uncorroborated beliefs by scores of
people. This question is though
quite relevant when trying to establish the validity of a particular brand of
faith, as Kelemen does with Judaism.
Next
Kelemen turns to what he calls "older religions." He reviews the foundations of Buddhism and Islam and indicates that both
religions are based on the claims of only one person, Gautama (Buddha) in one
case, and Mohammed, in the other. These stories, maintains Kelemen, are hard to
verify. For example, the Koran
reports some miraculous events which accompanied Mohammed's birth and
childhood as told by his mother. How
could a would-be Muslim know whether or not Mohammed's mother told the truth,
says Kelemen. He writes: (page 55)
"Someone who experiences or performs miracles (i.e. inexplicable phenomena)
might be unusually talented or wise, but he is not necessarily God's
messenger." True, and we can add to Kelemen's epithets "talented or
wise" also "skillful in magic" (like the scores of popular magicians
performing, for example, in Las Vegas' hotels).
Switching
to Christianity, Kelemen writes (page 55) that it "seems to boast a more
credible beginning." It becomes
clear, though, from the following text by Kelemen, that his apparent concession
to the "better credibility" of Christianity compared with Buddhism and Islam
is made by Kelemen not because he indeed views the claims of Christianity as
plausible, but because such an apparent concession is necessary if he wants to
give weight to his claims about the validity of Judaism.
As it
transpires from Kelemen's discourse, the "better credibility" of
Christianity is due to the fact that its beginning can be traced not to just one
founder, but to a group of twelve disciples. It is harder to believe, suggests Kelemen, that twelve people conspired
to lie than to suspect a single person of inventing a story about his direct
communication with God.
Having thus
made the described apparent concession to Christianity, Kelemen then proceeds to
convincingly demolish its story. He
describes the irreconcilable discrepancies between various Gospels. For example,
as we mentioned before, Matthew and Luke provide two irreconcilably different
versions of Jesus's genealogy. In
another example, Kelemen indicates the incompatibility of various reports about
Jesus' reappearance after his death and resurrection. Regarding the miracles Jesus reportedly performed in the presence of
crowds, Kelemen indicates justifiably that the Gospels fail to provide the names
of any alleged witnesses besides the twelve disciples, and, however rarely, but
twelve people could have conceivably conspired to lie. (The latter notions sounds rather tenuous. If we believe that the twelve disciples were real people, then,
reportedly, none of them had ever gained any advantages from their story, and,
on the contrary, all of them had suffered because of their faith). Kelemen repeats again that, even if we accept the stories about Jesus's
miracles, "none of them would prove that he was the messiah, let alone God.
Indeed, the Torah tells us about a Jewish prophet Elisha who revived the dead
(like Jesus) and poured a vast amount of oil from a tiny vial. Another Jewish prophet, Elija, ascended to the heaven alive. However, the Torah never implied that either of those prophets was a
Messiah or God."
These
remarks convincingly demonstrate the implausibility of the Gospels' story,
thus discrediting Kelemen's earlier bow to the alleged larger credibility of
Christianity's beginning.
Finally
Kelemen turns to Judaism.
As long as
Kelemen dealt with religions other than Judaism, his vision seemed to be
reasonably good, enabling him to discern discrepancies and inconsistencies in
those religious doctrines. Now, suddenly, his vision becomes blurred, depriving
him of the ability to see even the most glaring contradictions in his own
religious system. This sudden
change of the sharpness of vision reminds a well-known saying about one who
notices a blade of straw in somebody's eye but not a log in his own."
Kelemen's
main argument in favor of the Torah's plausibility is well known since it has
been repeated by many predecessors of Kelemen in a more or less similar form. The alleged proof of the Torah's veracity is found, Kelemen asserts, in
the story of the Exodus. The Torah's account of the exodus must be true, argues
Kelemen, because it asserts that the whole nation witnessed the miraculous
events described in the Torah (such as the splitting of the Red Sea at an
exactly proper moment, the ten plagues which befell Egypt, the miraculous
appearance of manna in the Sinai desert on weekdays but not on Saturdays, for
forty years in a row etc.). For
example, on page 66 Kelemen writes: "The most significant difference between
the Christianity's and Judaism's founding is not in the numbers - that only a few thousand of Jesus' followers witnessed his miracles
while millions of Jews heard God speak – rather the significance is in the
percentages... every Jew experienced the Sinai prophecy – 100 percent of a large
and easily identifiable population."
The quoted
statement is an epitome of what a Russian proverb refers to as an argument
"pulled in by grabbing ears," which means an extremely artificial and
unsubstantiated claim. Every part
of Kelemen's statement is grounded in quick sand.
First of
all, the entire argument is based on the Torah and nothing but the Torah, since
no independent corroborative evidence of the Exodus and of the related events
has been unearthed. All the valiant
efforts of archeologists to find any trace of the Exodus, of the wandering of
Israelites for forty years in Sinai, or of any other event described in the
Torah produced zero evidence of those events. The alleged exodus of millions of Jewish slaves from Egypt has not been
referred to even once in any of the numerous Egyptian sources of that epoch. The sheer number of the slaves – about 600,000 of men alone, who
allegedly escaped Egyptian bondage, irreconcilably contradicts other parts of
the Biblical story (like the repopulation of the world after the Flood starting
with only eight people just 1000 years before the Exodus, etc). Before using the story told in the Torah as the source for his argument
Kelemen should have first provided independent proof of that story's veracity. Of course, he could not do so because such proofs are not
available.
Furthermore,
even if, despite the absence of corroboration, we accepted the Torah's
narrative as a reliable historic account, Kelemen's argument still would
remain just an interpretation of the Torah's story, and a rather arbitrary
one.
Indeed, if we read the text of
the Torah, we find that nowhere does it unequivocally say that 100 percent of
the Jews witnessed Moses' communication with God. The closest to the assertion that the entire nation heard God speak is
found in two verses. One is Exodus
19:9 (in KJV translation): "And the LORD said unto
Moses, Lo, I come unto thee in a thick cloud, that the people may hear when I
speak with thee, and believe thee for ever" (Exodus 19:9). Unless one wants very much to assert that God spoke to the
entire nation, this verse actually only expresses God's intention to do so.
Further
we read: "And Moses brought forth the people out of the camp to meet with God;
and they stood at the nether part of the mount. And Mount Sinai was altogether
on a smoke, because the LORD descended upon it in fire: and the smoke thereof
ascended as the smoke of a furnace, and the whole mount quaked greatly. And when
the voice of the trumpet sounded long, and waxed louder and louder, Moses spake,
and God answered him by a voice" (Exodus 19:17-19).
In the Hebrew original, the expression translated "by a voice"
is bekol, which may be understood as
"loudly" – and if the people stood at the bottom of the mountain and God
spoke loudly, it may mean they heard God's voice. However, the real gist of that passage remains vague and there is no way
to conclude from it whether the people heard actual words, i.e. some message, or
simply some thunder-like sound.
We also read the following lines: "Did
ever people hear the voice of God speaking out of the midst of the fire, as thou
hast heard, and live?" (Deuteronomy 4:33).
It
is unclear from the tradition what exactly God had revealed to the People of
Israel at Mt. Sinai. On the one hand, the Torah says, after it lists again the
Ten Commandments in Deuteronomy, "These words the Lord spoke to all your
public at the mountain from the midst of the fire, of the cloud and of the thick
fog, with a great voice that did not cease" (Deuteronomy 5:19) – and from
this one may understand that all the Ten Commandments were revealed by God to
the whole people. On the other hand, the Talmud (Makot
24a) says that only the first two of the Ten
Commandments – "I am the Lord your God" and "You shall have no
other gods before Me" – were said by God directly to the people, and all
the others were told to Moses alone. The last view may be supported by the fact
that in the account of Exodus 20, the first two commandments speak of God in the
first person, while the remaining eight – in the third person ("You shall
have no other gods before Me" vs. "Do not bear the name of the Lord
your God in vain").
Nachmanides tried to explain this
contradiction by stating in his commentary on Exodus 20:7 that all the
Israelites heard all the Ten Commandments from the Divine, but they could
comprehend only the first two, and therefore, the last eight were repeated to
them by Moses.
Furthermore,.
Maimonides in "The Guide for the Perplexed" (part 2, chapter 33)
wrote the following: "It has become clear to me that at the Sinai Revelation,
what reached Moses did not reach all the Israelites, but His word reached Moses
alone...He, may he rest in peace, came down to the bottom of the mount and told
people what he heard [from God], as the Torah said, ' stood between the Lord
and you at that time.'(Deuteronomy 5:5), and it is also said, "Moses spoke,
and God answered him through a voice" (Exodus 19:19). And they interpreted it
in [Midrash] Mechilta that each phrase he [Moses] told them as he heard it [from
God]. It is also written in the Torah, 'that
the people may hear when I speak [with you]...'(Exodus 19:9) – and this
shows that God talked to him [Moses], but they [the people] heard that loud
voice, but did not distinguish the words. And it is also said, "You hear the
voice of speech" (Deuteronomy 4:12) – but not, 'you hear the speech,'
But... they heard the voice, and Moses was that who heard the speech
[of God] and told it to the people – this is what comes out of the Torah and
of the most of the Sages' words."
(There is also an opinion brought in many places in the Midrash
and even in the Talmud, that when He said "I am [the Lord your God]" and
"You shall not have [other gods] before Me," they heard it directly from the
mouth of the Glory.")
Hence,
according to Maimonides, from the Torah itself one can understand that during
the Sinai Revelation the people heard nothing definite from God, but all the
commandments were revealed to Moses alone, who then told them to the people –
and the story that the first two of the Ten Commandments were told by God
directly to the whole People of Israel is only a view of a minority of the
Sages. Each commentator has his own view, but none of them claims it was from a
tradition he received from his ancestors and rabbis. Everyone of them tries to
form a view, based on what is said in the Scripture, the Talmud and the Midrash.
If we
re-read the Torah's story ourselves, we find that on each occasion when Moses
communicated with God he was either alone (as when he spent forty days and
nights on the summit of Mount Sinai) or was accompanied only by Aaron, and once
by Joshua (Yehoshua). Also, on one
occasion seventy elders climbed the mountain and saw God. This story is rather far from the assertion that the entire nation
witnessed anything more than an earthquake, thunder and lightning.
Essentially,
Kelemen's argument boils down to the assertion that generations of Jews would
not accept the Torah's story were it not true and not transmitted through
generations, supposedly going back to the time of Moses. However, the history of various religions demonstrates that scores of
people accept all kinds of legendary stories without a plausible proof of them,
and transmit their beliefs through the generations. For example, the population of the Khazar empire had been pagans for many
hundred years. In the middle of 8th
century CE the ruler of that empire decided to convert to Judaism, his decision
based on political reasons. Following
his example, a substantial fraction of the empire's population converted to
Judaism as well. Obviously, these
newly converted Jews had no tradition which could be traced back even a couple
of generations let alone to Moses' times. However, only a few generations after the conversion these people had
already completely lost the memory of ever having been non-Jews. They already viewed themselves as genuine transmitters of the ancient
tradition traced to Moses and believed themselves to be descendants of
Jacob/Israel. In the ancient Slavic legends they were already referred to, to
distinguish them from the rest of the Khazars, not as Khazars but as "Zhidovins" (Jews). Obviously, the Slavs would not change the name they used for their
neighbors if that part of the Khazars themselves did not adopt the new name,
which Russian transliterated as Zhidovins. On the other hand, the Slavic tribes
also were pagans for centuries. In
the year of 980 the most powerful warlord of the Slavs, Vladimir, adopted
Christianity, and forced the population of his realm to undergo baptism. Just a
few generations later the national memory of the Russians and Ukrainians lost
any trace of their pagan past, and they became some of the most ardent Christian
believers despite the fact that their religious tradition was of recent origin. These examples show that traditions can take root very rapidly without
being based on a transmission through many generations and regardless of whether
or not those traditions could be considered by Kelemen as substantiated by
historical evidence. Could not the
tradition of the Middle-Eastern Jews have been formed in a similar manner?
In
view of the above, Kelemen's assertion (page 74) that "Those who would
affirm the Torah's divinity stand on intellectually firm ground" may only
cause one to wonder whether Kelemen views his readers as men and women with at
least a minimal capacity for logical thought or his intention is to prohibit his
readers to think.
The
second half of Kelemen's second book is titled "Two Issues: Responses to Two
Arguments against the Torah's Divine Origin." The first of the issues in question is what Kelemen calls "The
Empirical Issue." In the
section devoted to that subject, Kelemen discusses scientific data allegedly
confirming the veracity of the Torah. At the very beginning of that section
(page 81) Kelemen writes: "Once we detect one or several inaccuracies in a
document, we have reason to suspect its entire text." It is easy to accept that notion. A
natural question is then, why the obvious inaccuracies in the story told by the
Torah have failed to raise any suspicion in regard to its entire text in
Kelemen's mind?
The
inaccuracies in question are numerous. We
have discussed earlier in this article the incompatibility of the Torah's two
pieces of information – only eight survivals of the Flood and 2.5 million of
only Jews just 1,000 years later. At
least one of these two reports, and possibly both must be inaccurate. Kelemen says on the same page: "If the Torah contains such
inaccuracies, we would have to take a sizable leap of faith to believe that the
Sinaitic revelation really happened." Very
true, Mr. Kelemen, and we are entitled to expect from you adherence to your own
criteria. Instead, Kelemen resorts to verbal acrobatics, trying to
prove that the Torah contains no inaccuracies.
As do
many other writers in the same genre, Kelemen mobilizes modern theories of
physics as allegedly supporting the Biblical narrative. Of course, the first such theory is that of the Big Bang. To evaluate the quality of Kelemen's discourse in this matter, it seems
sufficient to point out that he uses as one of his main tools a reference to G.
Schroeder. Kelemen writes: "Dr.
Gerald Schroeder of M.I.T. explains that the energy released in the first moment
of the Big Bang radiated at such high frequencies that it would have been
invisible to the human eye..." etc.
G.
Schroeder is not "of M.I.T." He
is a lecturer at Aish HaTorah, an organization that propagandizes the tenets of
Judaism and thus prods those Jews who have lost faith or are skeptical about it,
to return to fold. In other words,
Schroeder is a professional propagandist for the Torah's veracity. His book,
referred to by Kelemen, contains numerous inaccuracies and errors testifying to
Schroeder's insufficient understanding of physics in general and of the Big
Bang theory in particular. Using
Shcroeder's book as an alleged proof of the Torah's compatibility with
science simply shows Kelemen's own lack of scientific background and
comprehension. Moreover, even if we accept that a certain statement in the
Biblical story is compatible with some scientific data, it is still very far
from being a proof of the whole story. For
example, imagine a person accused of a crime and having no alibi. Having no alibi is compatible with a suggestion that the person in
question is guilty, but it in itself does not constitute a proof of guilt. If some assertion in the Torah does not contradict some scientific data,
this in itself is not proof of that statement's veracity. On the other hand, if some statement in the Torah contradicts some
scientific data, it is indeed a strong argument against the veracity of at least
of that particular statement in the Torah. Based on Kelemen's criterion quoted above, inaccuracy of a particular
statement casts shadow on the veracity of the entire document. An example immediately coming to mind is the Torah's story
about the six days of creation, which irreconcilably contradicts
well-established scientific data. Pointing
to some elements in the Torah that seem not to contradict science and
unreasonably maintaining that mentioning this absence of contradiction is proof
of the Torah's story, Kelemen seems not to notice those numerous elements of
the Torah which disprove his contention.
Continuing his discussion,
Kelemen quotes certain publications regarding the possible descent of the entire
humankind from a common ancestor. First,
the quoted data are inconclusive and are in the process of further study whose
results are hard to predict. Second, Kelemen, strangely, is not concerned with
the immense discrepancy between the data he quotes (which indicate that the
alleged common ancestor of the entire humankind lived hundreds of thousands of
years ago) and the Biblical story (which asserts that the first man was created
only about 6,000 years ago). If the
scientific data in question are confirmed, will this not make the mentioned
discrepancy in time spans that inaccuracy which, as Kelemen asserted in the
beginning of the chapter, make the entire text suspicious?
Then Kelemen discusses the
biblical story of the Flood, where he again tries to break through an open door
by citing various ancient sources that report on massive floods in the distant
past. The question, though, is not
whether or not massive floods occurred in the past, since there is little doubt
that the answer is "Yes." The veracity of the Biblical account is suspicious
not in regards to the question whether there were large floods but because of
the numerous details of that story which are utterly implausible. It is implausible that four men who had no experience in shipbuilding,
had no tools and proper materials, could build a seaworthy ship with about
55,000 tons of displacement, that they could have gathered representatives of
all the animals, and provided victuals for them for several months, that the
entire earth was covered by water etc. Hence,
all of Kelemen's discussion aimed at proving that a big flood did indeed occur
in the distant past is immaterial and does not prove in the least the veracity
of the Biblical account.
The next part of Kelemen's
discussion is even worse, when he claims that archeological data support the
biblical story about the patriarchs. This statement is untrue. The overwhelming
conclusion by Israeli archeologists (for example, expressed by an Israeli
archeologist professor Zeev Hertzog of Tel-Aviv University in Haaretz newspaper
on October 29, 1999) is that, despite earlier expectations, there are practically no archeological
data compatible with the Biblical story, including the Exodus, the sojourn in
Sinai, the conquest of Canaan under Yehoshua Bin-Nun, etc, until the epoch of
the Kings. As to the period of the
Patriarchs, Professor Hertzog indicates that the archeological studies even
failed to date that period. Therefore,
in view of recent advances in archeological science in Israel, all references by
Kelemen to archeological data must be taken with caution.
To discuss in detail all of
Kelemen's argumentation based on his comparison of scientific and historical
data with the Biblical story would require to write a book about the same size
as his. I will therefore limit
my discussion only to the listed examples, stating though that the rest of
Kelemen's discourse is no more convincing than the items covered so far.
The second chapter in that part
of Kelemen's second book is
titled "The Ethical Issue." It
contains a compilation of statistical data showing, according to Kelemen, that
the Jewish people have been profoundly affected by the moral principles
expounded in the Torah and therefore they display distinctive trends of morality
exceeding those of many other ethnic and religious groups. While that discussion leaves out many important facts which in some
instances could undermine Kelemen's thesis, I choose to stop my discussion of
Kelemen's two books right here, since regardless of his being fully or
partially correct or not, this thesis has only a tangential relation to the
question of the Torah's origin, and even less to the question of God's
existence.
My review was only in relation
to the above indicated two questions. My overall conclusion is that Kelemen
failed to convincingly support his contentions and rather than appealing to his
readers to "permit" themselves "to believe and to receive," he subtly
(and sometimes not very subtly) attempted to impose on his readers a prohibition
to think.
Mark Perakh's main page.
|
|